Paternalism and Patient Autonomy.
Paternalism and Patient Autonomy
On its face, the relationship between patient and health caxe plovlder seems technically simple and morally clear. The provider–physician, nurse, physician’s assistant, or other professional–has a duty of beneficence toward the patient, an ob- ligation to use her medical expertise to do him good and to avoid doing him harm. The patient has a right to this skilled beneficence and to re- spect for his autonomous choices regarding what the provider does. But below the surface, com- plications simmer. The principles of beneficence and autonomy are frequently at odds The val- ues of providers and patients can diverge. The cultures of patients, physicians, and nurses can clash. And often the stakes for everyone involved are extraordinarily high
Save your time - order a paper!
Get your paper written from scratch within the tight deadline. Our service is a reliable solution to all your troubles. Place an order on any task and we will take care of it. You won’t have to worry about the quality and deadlines
Order Paper NowIn this chapter we explole several moral issues arising from these conflicts, focusing on ques- tions of medical paternalism, refusing treatment, and “futile” treatment Chapter 4 delves into other aspects of patient-provider relationships, notably truth-telling, deception, and confiden- tiality. Chapter 5 examines the patient-provider relationship further by studying the many sides of informed consent and patient competence.
SHADES OF AUTONOMY AND PATERNALISM
Autonomy is a person’s rational capacity for self- governance or self-determination. It is an individ- ual’s power to deliberate about available options, to choose freely among those posslbthtles, and to act accordingly. We fully exercise our autonomy when our choices and actions are truly our own, flee from the overriding pressure of people and factors that rob us of control. The requirement to
respect autonomy runs through all of bioethics, expressed in the autonomy principle, which we can state as autonomous persons should be allowed to exercise their capacity for self-determination. In bloethics it is considered a fundamental stan- dard that can be violated only for good reasons and with explicit justification. In the name of the autonomy principle, medicine has developed the doctrine of informed consent and has devised countless procedures and guidelines to ensure that the principle IS honoied in the details.
Limitations on a person’s autonomy can be physical or psychological, obvious or subtle, jus- tiffed or unjustified, and generally accepted or widely controversial. Physically restraining a pa- tient violates his autonomy, and so does misin- forming him about the seriousness of his illness. Forcing a healthy woman to have a hysterectomy is obvious coercion. Using false information to persuade her to have the operation is a subtler kind of compulsion. We tend to think that phy- sicians are sometnnes justified In confining and treating a mentally ill man who is a danger to himself and others. We would not think so if the man were perfectly healthy Giving a 12-year-old girl a blood transfusion to save her life seems hke normal medical practice. Withholding the trans- fusion because her parents say it is an affront to their religious faith is controversial.
Conflicts between respect for patients’ auton- omy and providers’ duty of beneficence usually raise the issue of paternalism, which we can de- fine as the overriding of a person’s actions or de- cision-making for hÿs own good. Early medical practice was strongly paternalistic, inspired by the Hippocratic tradition of devotion to the welfare of patients and fatherly insistence on deciding
72 PAR3 2″ HEDICAL PROPESSIONAL AND PATIENT Chapter 3. Patmnahsm and Patient Autonomy 73
unilaterally what is best for them. The Hippo- cratic Oath and many later professional codes of medical practice had much to say about obliga- tions to help and not to haim patients but little or nothing to declare about patients’ rights to de- cide about their own medical care But over the last few decades, this Mnd of heaw-handed pa- ternalism has abated as society has placed more value on the rights of patients to know important facts about their medical care, to make choices regarding their medical treatment, and even to refuse treatment that physicians recommend.
We can distinguish between two kinds of paternalism. Weak paternalism refers to pa- ternalism directed at peisons who cannot act autonomously or whose autonomy is greatly diminished–who may be, for example, danger- ously psychotic, severely retarded, extremely de- pressed, or acutely addicted Weak paternalism is not usually considered an objectionable vio- lation of autonomy because patients are already substantially nonautonomous to some degree Generally it is thought to be morally acceptable because its purpose is to protect people from harm while they are nonautonomous, to deter- mine if they are in fact nonautonomous, or to re- store them to full autonomy. Strong paternalism is the overriding of a person’s actions or choices even though he is substantially autonomous Cases involving strong paternalism often pro- voke debate and sometimes legal wrangling. A man who normally behaves autonomously and rationally IS involuntarily committed to a men- tal institution because he occasionally becomes confused and disoriented and doctors fear that he might someday become a threat to himself or others. A physician discovers that his patient has a malignant breast tumor, but because he knows she is terrified of the disease, he tells her that the tumor is benign and should be surgi- cally removed just in case A woman who needs a life-saving blood transfusion refuses it on reli- gious grounds, but when she lapses into a coma, surgeons operate and give her the transfusion anyway These and other scenarios play out more
often than we might think and prompt not only ethical disagreement but also personal and pro- fesslonal anguish.
Many people are staunchly antl-paternahstlc, condoning (as most do) acts of weak paternal- ism but rejecting all forms of strong paternalism. They argue that strong paternalism is wrong be- cause it violates the rights of persons to deter- mine for themselves what is good and what is right. Persons are sovereigns over their own lives, and overriding their sovereignty is impermissi- ble regardless of the benefits gained by violating it. Others are more willing to countenance some acts of paternalism (including strong paternal- ism) on the grounds that the persons revolved would consent to the acts if circumstances were ideal (if, say, the persons were thinking more ra- tionally). These thinkers, for example, might be willing to commit a substantially autonomous person to a mental institution involuntarily if he would have trouble living independently and might be a danger to himself. Still others argue that the only satisfactory justification for pater- nalism is not consent but beneficence–interven- ing simply to promote someone’s welfare. On this view, the benefits ofpaternahstic actions must be balanced against the importance of respecting autonomy. Actions that minimally restrict au- tonomy but benefit the person greatly would be justified; actions that seriously violate autonomy while offering only minor benefits would not be acceptable. Far less important would be concerns about what the individual would or would not consent to under different circumstances?
REFUSING TREATMENT
Patients want physicians to treat them; physi- cians want to treat patients. But often when patients (or their surrogates) refuse treatment, patient autonomy and physician beneficence collide, sparldng personal frustration and moral perplexity all around. In such cases the most vex- ing bioethical questions include: Is it ever mor- ally permissible for a physician to treat a patient
For centuries the Hippocratic Oath has been one of the great mspwauons for Western medmal etNcs It is one of several writings attributed to an ancmnt Greek school of medicine whose head was Hip- pocrates, born about 460 B C.
I swear by Apollo Physmlan and Asclepius and Hy#eia and Panaceia and all the gods and god- desses, making them my wimess, that I will fulfill according to my abdlty and ludgment tNs oath and tNs covenant:
To hold him who has taught me this art as equal to my parents and to hve my life in partnershtp wÿth hm, and ff he Is m need of money to give him a share of mine, and to regard Ns offspring as equal to my brothers m male hneage and to teach them tNs art–if they deswe to learn tt–wJthout fee and covenant;
to give a share of precepts and oral mstructton and all the other learning to my sons and to the sons of Nm who has instructed me and to pupils who have signed the covenant and have taken an oath according to the medmal law, but to no one else
I will apply dJeteuc measures for the benefit of the sml< according to my ability and ludgment; I will keep them from harm and mlUSUCe.
I will neither #ve a deadly drug to anybody if asked for ut, nor wdl I make a suggesUon to tNs effect. Similarly I will not give to a woman an aboruve remedy. In purity and holiness I will guard my hfe and my art
I will not use the knife, not even on sufferers from stone, but will withdraw m favor of such men as are engaged m this work.
Whatever houses I may visit, I will come for the benefit of the sick, remaining free of all mten- uonal mlusuce, of all mtscNef and m parucular of sexual relauons with both female and male per- sons, be they free or slaves.
What I may see or hear in the course of the treatment or even outside of the treatment m regard to the life of men, whmh on no account one must spread abroad, I wdl keep to myself holding such things shameful to be spoken about
If I fulfill tNs oath and do not wolate ÿt, may it be granted to me to enloy hfe and art, being honored with fame among all men for all ume to come; ff I transgress it and swear falsely, may the opposite of all this be my lot.
From Ludwig Edelstem, Ancient Medicine Selected Papers of Ludwig Edelstem, ed Owsel Temkm and C Ldhan Temkm (Baltimore Johns Hopkins Umverslty Press, 1967), 3-65
against her will? If so, what justifies the action, and under what conditions is it acceptable?
Until the late 1980s, the right of competent pa- tients to turn down treatments ordered by phy- sicians was unsettled. (Very roughly, competent patients are autonomous persons able to make decisions about treatment options.) In some situ- ations, patients were thought to have no right to dedine recommended treatments. Physicians sometimes forced pregnant patients to have ce- sarean deliveries if failure to do so put the fetuses at extreme risk. The courts frequently overruled the right to refuse treatment if the patient had
dependent children or if the patIeut was not ter- minally 111. But later court rulings reversed the trend and carved out the bedrock principle that a competent patient has a right to reject recom- mended treatments, even life-saving ones. The legal principle now parallels the prevailing view in bioethlcs, which shifts the weight to patient au- tonomy over physician and nurse beneficence.
• he courts have also stretched this right of competent patients to situations in which they be- come incompetent, as when they lapse Into coma. Through advance directives or other evidence of their preferences, they can refuse life-sustaining
7 4
P A
R T
2 : H
E D
IC A
L P
[ÿO F
E ÿS
IO N
A L
A N
D P
t= ÿ|IE
N T
A ÿa
p te
r 3 , P
a ÿe
ÿm h
sm a
n d
P a
, tm n
t A u
to n
o m
y 7 5
tre a
tm e
n t T
h ts e
xp re
ssto n
o f p
rio r in
te n
tio n
s is now
w idely recognized as a legitim
ate exercise of autonom
ous choice. The right to refuse treatm
ent seem s a relatively
stt aightforw ard issue w
hen the patient is a com pe-
tent adult, but w hat if the patient ts a child w
hose p
a te
n ts re
je ct th
e re
co m
m e
n d
e d
m e
d tca
l tre a
t- m
ent on religious grounds? C onsider the case of
ll-ye a r-o
ld Ia
n L
u n d m
a n o
f M m
n e a p o h s, M
m –
nesota, w ho dted on M
ay 9, 1989, after shpplng into a diabetic com
a H ts diabetes had rem
ained m
edically untreated, his m other and stepfather
forgoing insulin in favor of prayels from C
hris- tian S
cience practlttoners.2 (C hristian S
cientists believe that disease is a spiritual &
sorder requir- ing spm
tual healing, not m edical treatm
ent.) O r
constder thts scenario, typical of such cases: A 6-
year-old girl is seriously injured m a traffic acci-
dent, and the only w ay to save her life ts to give hm
a blood transfusion–w hich her Jehovah’s W
itness parents reject because the procedure is explicitly forbidden by their faith. The physicians proceed w
ith the transfusion and save the gnl’s life, and the patents sue the physicians and the hospital.
P arents w
ho for religious reasons reject m edi-
cal treatm ent foi their children m
sist on the right to &
ode w hat’s best for them
and sincerely be- lieve w
hat’s best ts avoiding m edical interven-
tions. 3hey dem and the freedom
to practice their rehgton as they see fit. B
ut others have argued (including the courts) that though parents m
ay decide m
any m atters on the w
ell-being of their children, they do not have the right to bring se- rious harm
to them , especially since children
cannot decide such tssues for them selves. T
his view
w as sum
m ed up in a fam
ous 1944 S uprem
e C
oult dectsion: “P arents m
ay be free to becom e
m altyrs them
selves. B ut tt does not follow
they a te
fre e ., to
m a ke
m a rtyrs o
fth m
r ch ild
re n :’3
T he sttuatlon takes on a different hue w
hen children are considered com
petent to decide for them
selves. S tates dtffer on w
hether an adoles- cent can be a “m
ature m inor” to m
ake health de- cisions, and the courts have w
affled on the issue Judges have ruled, for exam
ple, that a 15-year-old Jehovah’s W
itness gift dying of leukem ia could
refuse a blood transfuston that w ould save her
life –b
u t th
a t a
1 6 -ye
a r-o
ld b
o y in
ju re
d m
a tra
in accident could not decline a transfusion needed d u rin
g su
rg e ry to
sa ve
h is a
rm . N
e ve
rth e le
ss, m
a n
y a rg
u e
th a
t if a d
o le
sce n
ts a re
n o
t co m
p e
– tent to dectde such things, com
petent adults (in- cluding phystcians and nurses) should step tn to p
ro te
ct th e
ir w e
lfa re
, e ve
n if m
te rve
n ln
g m
e a
n s
defying religious doctrine.
F U
T ILE
T R
E A
T M
E N
T
The classic pattern ofpatei nahsm involves a phy-
sician w ho w
ants to treat a patient w ho prefers
not to be treated. B ut som
ehm es things happen
th e o
th e r w
a y a
ro u n d –w
h e n th
e p
a tie
n t o
r th e
patient’s fam ily w
ants a tIeatm ent that the phys>
ctan, typtcally fiom beneficent m
otives, does not w
a n
t to p
ro vid
e . T
h e
m a
in m
o ra
l co n
flict is b e
– tw
een patient autonom y and the physician’s view
of w hat constitutes m
oially acceptable care. The m
ost dram atic (and heart-rending) of such
cases center on w hether to supply hfe-sustaxnlng
tteatm ent to the pattent. C
onstder the m uch dis-
cussed story of 85-year-old H elga W
anglie, w ho
in 1990 suddenlyhad to be placed on a ventilator because of serious breathing problem
s. O ver the
follow ing w
eeks, her condition w orsened as she
sank into unconsciousness and then into a per- ststent vegetattve state (a deep com
a that is usu- ally lrrevelsible). S
he received round-the-dock hfe-sustalnlng tieatm
ent consisting of ventilator, a
n tib
io tics, tu
b e
fe e
d in
g s, a
n d
o th
e r m
e a
su re
s B
ut physictans told H elga’s husband and tw
o children that the treatm
ent w as not helping her
and should be stopped. H er fam
ily, how ever, de-
m anded that the treatm
ent continue. They hoped for a m
iracle and asserted that H elga w
as not bet- ter off dead and that physlctans should not play G
od. H er husband clatm
ed that H elga had never
exD essed an opinion about life-sustainm
g treat- m
ent for heiself. Later a second team of physi-
cians confirm ed the view
s of the first, calling the ve
n tila
to r “n
o n b e n e ficta
l” b e ca
u se
It co u ld
n o t
ease H elga’s sufferm
g, repatr her body, or help her experience life.
R e
fu s in
g T
re a
tm e
n t fo
r C h
ild re
n o
n R
e lig
io u
s G ro
u n
d s
S ince the 1970s, several chddren have dm
d after thew parents refused m
edm al treatm
ent because of reh- gious behefs. The deaths have sparked fierce debates and legal confhcts, w
ith som e lurtsdtcuons offering
rehgious parents exem puons from
child abuse and neglect law
s w hde m
edical orgam zauons such as
the Am erm
an Academ y of Pedlam
cs (AAP) and the A
m erm
an M edm
al A ssoclauon (A
M A
) have opposed the law
s In its pohcy statem ent on the ÿssue, the
A A
P declares, “C
onsutuuonal guarantees of free- dom
of rehglon do not perm it cN
Idren to be harm ed
through rehgJous pracuces, nor do they allow reh-
glon to be a vahd defense w hen an Individual harm
s or neglects a cN
Id.” A ccording to a recent tally of the
religious exem puons.
T hw
ty-nm e states and the D
Istrm t of C
olum N
a have rehglous exem
ptions m their ow
l codes on child abuse or neglect, largely because of a federal governm
ent policy from 1974 to 1983
requw m
g states to pass such exem ptions in
order to get federal funding for child protecuon w
ork The states are A labam
a, A laska, A
H zona,
A rkansas, C
aliform a, C
olorado, C onnecucut,
D elaw
are, Florida, G eorgia, Idaho, Illinois,
Indiana, Iow a, K
ansas, K entucky, Louisiana,
M aine, M
m N
gan, M innesota, M
ississippi, M
issouri, M ontana, N
evada, N ew
H am
pshw e,
N ew
Jersey, N ew
M exico, N
orth D akota,
O ldahom
a, O regon, P
ennsylvania, R hode
Island, S outh C
arohna, U tah, V
erm ont, V
w gm
la, W
ashington, W isconsin, and W
yom ing
A dditionally, Tennessee exem
pts caretakers
w ho w
ithhold m edical care from
being adludm
ated as negligent ff they rely instead on nonm
edm al “rem
edial treatm ent” that Is “legally
recogm zed or legally perm
itted.” N
ineteen states have rebgÿous defenses to felony crim
es against chddren A rkansas,
D e
la w
a re
, Id a
h o
, In d
ia n
a , Io
w a
, K a
n sa
s,
Lom slana, M
innesota, N ew
Jersey, O hm
, O
ldahom a, O
regon, R hode Island, Tennessee,
U tah, V
lrgm m
, W ashington, W
est V irginia, and
W isco
n sin
Eleven states have rehgÿous defenses to m
isdem eanors A
labam a, A
laska, C ahfornla,
C olorado, G
eorgia, N am
e, N evada, N
ew H
am pshm
e, N ew
Y ork, S
outh C arohna, and
S outh D
akota M issouri exem
pts parents from the m
ÿsdem eanor charges of endangerm
ent and nonsupport ff they provide “nonm
edm al rem
edial treatm
ent recognized and perm itted under the
law s of thÿs state” instead of m
edm al care
Florida has a rehgJous exem puon only m
the ow
l code, but the F lorida S
uprem e C
ourt nevertheless held that ÿt caused confusion about crim
inal habdW and requm
ed overturning a felony convÿcuon of C
hnsuan S oenusts for
lem ng them
daughter die of untreated dm betes
S tates w
ÿth a rehgious defense to the m ost serious
crÿm es against children include’
• Iow a and O
hto, w ith religious defenses to
m anslaughter
• D elaw
are and W est V
w gm
ta, w tth rehglous
defenses to m urder of a chtld
• A rkansas, w
ÿth a rehgious defense to capital m
urder • O
regon, w ith a rehgtous defense to hom
m lde
by abuse4
T he struggle over w
hether to dlscontm ue
H e lg
a ‘s tre
a tm
e n t e
ve n tu
a lly m
o ve
d in
to co
u rt,
but its decision did little to resolve the stalem ate.
Three days after the court ruling, H elga died.s
S uchphysician-patlent conflicts are com
m only
described as confrontations about m edical futil-
ity, the alleged pom tlessness or ineffectiveness of
a d
m m
tste rln
g p
a rticu
la r tre
a tm
e n
ts. P h
ysm ia
n s
76 P
A R
T 2
. N E
D IC
A L
P R
O F
E S
S IO
N A
L A
N D
P A
I’IE N
T C
h a p te
r 3 ‘ P
a L e Jrÿa
h sm
a n d P
a tm
rlt A u to
n o rn
y 1 7
T he m
edical procedure used to restart a person’s heart and breathing is know
n as cardlopulm onary re-
suscitation, or C P
R . It typically consists of m
outh-to- m
outh resuscitation and external chest com pression
but m ay involve m
ore advanced procedures such as defibrillation (electric shock to restore norm
al heart rhythm
). A do-not-resuscitate order, or D
N R
, is a dw
ectlve telling the m edical staff to forgo C
P R
on a patient ff hÿs heart or breathing stops D
N R
or-
ders are generally thought to be m edically appropri-
ate and m orally perm
issible w hen the perform
ing of C
P R
on seriously or term inally Ill patients w
ould be ineffective or futile and w
ould only prolong dying or intensify the patient’s pain and suffering. P
atients can co
n se
n t to
D N
R o
rd e
rs m p
e rso
n , m
w ritte
n in
stru c-
tions m an advance dw
ectÿve such as a hw ng w
ill, or through som
eone they designate as thew representa-
tw e, or proxy The A
H A
declares, “The physm B
an has an ethm
al obhgation to honor the resuscitation pref- erences expressed by the patient. P
hyslaans should not perm
it thew personal value judgm
ents about quahty of hfe to obstruct the im
plem entation of a
patient’s preferences regarding the use of C P
R ”
a s u
se le
ss, o r th
e p
a tm
n t d
ie s. B
u t so
m e
tim e
s resolution eludes everyone. The sharpest clash of values is likely to occur betw
een physicians and those w
ho argue for the sanctity of hum an life
O n this view
, the m oral im
perative is to keep the body alive at all costs. For som
eone w ho accepts
this principle, the physicians’ claim that the treat-
m ent does not benefit the patient w
ill carry little w
eight. A com
m on argum
ent against the position is that It m
akes no sense to treat a body w hen the
person w hose body it is no longer exists.
The m ajor m
oral theories im ply diverse stands on
paternalism . A
s a theory driven by the principle of beneficence, utilitarianisin dem
ands that w e
m a xim
ize th
e g
o o d fo
r e ve
ryo n e in
vo lve
d –a
re –
quirem ent that m
ay justify paternalistic actions. T
o p
ro m
o te
th e
g re
a te
st g o
o d
fo r p
a tie
n ts–to
m in
im ize
su ffe
rin g a
n d m
a xim
ize w
e ll-b
e in
g –a
physician or nurse m ay think it som
etim es legiti-
m ate to breach confidentiality or m
islead patients about their condition or proposed treatm
ent. S he
m ay believe it m
orally perm issible to override a
patient’s refusal of treatm ent or to reject the use
of requested treatm ents thought to be futile.
A ct- a
n d
ru le
-u tilita
ria n
s ca n
d isa
g re
e d
ra –
m atically on such m
atters. (They m ay also differ
m ay claim
that a treatm ent IS
futile and there- fore should not be used or continued. P
atients or their surrogates m
ay reject the label of futihty and insist that everything be done that can be done. B
ut physicians and patients often have different ideas about w
hat constitutes futility. The form er
m ay judge a treatm
ent futile if it cannot achieve a specified physiological benefit (cannot, for exam
ple, repair tissue, restore functioning, or ease suffering); the latter m
ay think a treatm ent futile
only if it cannot keep the body alive. For both, the issue of futility is a question of values–of w
hat should be done in the circum
stances. In tugs of w
ar over the acceptability of treat- m
ent, physicians appeal to a w idely recognized
principle: P hysicians are not obligated to pro-
vid e
tre a
tm e
n ts th
a t a
re In
co n
siste n
t w ith
re a
– sonable standards of m
edical practice. They are not m
orally bound to com ply, for exam
ple, w hen
a patient requests that his legs be am putated for
no reason or dem ands injections of a w
orthless and dangerous cancer rem
edy. N ot every patient
request m ust be regarded as legitim
ate, and not every m
edical technology m ust be supplied.
M any tim
es in futility cases, physicians and surrogates find resolution. T
hey agree to an exten- sion of the treatm
ent for a specified period or to reasonable goals that the treatm
ent can achieve, or the surrogates eventually view
the treatm ent
?%
C rm
cally im portant bloethm
al issues can arise for nurses from
thew relatÿonsN
ps w ÿth patm
nts, w ÿth
physicians, and w ith the institutional ethm
under w
hich they serve A
s nurses interact w ith patm
nts, they m ust com
e to term
s w ith m
any of the sam e m
oral questions and principles that w
m gh so heaw
ly on physicaans’ be- neficence versus patm
nt autonom y, patÿent-prow
der confidentiality, truth-telhng, refusal of treatm
ent, in- form
ed consent, and futde treatm ent.
The issues generated from physm
lan-nurse rater- actions can be just as pressing. The tradm
onal notion of a nurse ÿs that of a caregÿver subordinate to physi- cians and duty bound to carry out their dw
ectw es
for patm nt care and treatm
ent. B ut for m
any nurses
this m odel seem
s fraught w ith confhcts betw
een the nurse’s obhgatlon to follow
the doctor’s orders and her duty of beneficence tow
ard her panents S he m
ay w
onder w hether she has this sort of duty to physi-
cians even w hen thew
orders seem clearly to be Jn
error, or hkely to harm her patm
nts, or obw ously m
violation of patients’ autonom y, or ew
dently contrary to w
ell-established standards of care. S
o m
e w
rite rs h
a ve
d e
fe n
d e
d th
e tra
d itio
n a
l m
odel of nursing, arguing that (at least m hospitals)
physm lans m
ust alw ays be the ultim
ate authority on treatm
ent in urgent or serious cases. A fter all, only
doctors have the reqm slte training and experience
to deal w ith such situations, and for the sake of effi-
ciency, thew decisfons should not be quem
oned. The nurse’s proper role Is therefore subservient
B ut others reject the tradm
onal m odel, arguing m
– stead that the nurse’s ultim
ate responslbdlty is to be an advocate for patients, that adopting a subserw
ent role w
ould hkely harm patients, and that blindly follow
ing physm
ians’ orders does not serve the patient w ell
in theii estam ates of the probablhties involved and
ideas about the nature of the good to be m ax>
m ize
d .) In
a ct-u
tilita ria
n ism
, th e
iig h
tn e
ss o f a
c- tions depends on the relative good produced by in
d ivid
u a
l a ctio
n s, in
ru le
-u tilita
ria n
ism , rig
h t-
ness depends on the good m axim
ized by rules governing categories of actions. O
n act-utilitaiian grounds, a physician m
ay judge that it is m orally
perm issible to lie to a patient about a beneficial
treatm ent to overcom
e the patient’s refusal to be treated. B
ut based on rule-utihtarianlsm , a physi-
cian m ay believe that in the long run, lies do m
ore harm
than good because they erode public trust in the m
edical profession. B etter to adhere to a
rule barring deceit as a m eans of getting patients
to accept a treatm ent.
U tilitarians w
ho follow John S
tuart M all’s lead,
how ever, w
ould reject such paternalism . M
all be- lieves that the principle of utility im
plies a strong respect for individual self-determ
ination and as- se
rts th a t n
o o
n e m
a y in
te rfe
re w
ith a
p e rso
n ‘s
liberty except to prevent harm to others A
s M ill
says, “[A person] cannot nghtfully be com
pelled to do or forbear because it w
ill be better for him to
d o so
, b e ca
u se
It w ill m
a ke
h im
h a p p ie
r, b e –
cause, in the opinion of others, to do so w ould be
w ise, or even right”6 O
n this view people should
typlcaU y be perm
itted to decide w hat is to be
d o
n e
to th
e ir o
w n
b o
d ie
s, to re
fu se
tre a
tm e
n ts,
and to give their Inform ed consent.
G enerally, K
antian ethics also rejects pater- n
a h
sm . T
h e
m e
a n
s-e n
d fo
rm o
f th e
ca te
g o
rica l
im perative insists on respect foi the rights and
a u to
n o m
y o f p
e rso
n s–re
sp e ct th
a t m
u st n
o t b
e w
eakened by calculations of utility and paternal- istic urges to act for the patient’s ow
n good. T he
principle w ould require physicians to honor a
patient’s decision to refuse treatm ent, even w
hen they believe the treatm
ent is life-saving. Inform ed
consent of the patient for any treatm ent w
ould be m
andatory, and m isleading the patient about
treatm ent w
ould be out of the question. T o ignore
1 8 P
A R
t 2 : 1
“4 E
D IC
A L P
R O
F E
S S
IO N
[A L A
ÿD P
A T
![ÿN T
C h
a p
te r 3
‘ P a
te }n
a h
sm a
tÿd P
a tie
n t A
u to
n o
m y 1
9
E lizabeth B
ouvia
//
into her nose to her stom ach, a procedure know
n as nasogastrm
feeding. O pm
lons am ong m
edical pro- fesslonals about the practice w
ere m ixed, w
ith som e
saying that it w as necessary and others that tt w
as horrible and coercive, am
ounting to battery. B
ouvta lost an appeal of the ludge’s decision, w as
later transferred to another hospital, and eventually ended up at H
igh D esert H
ospital, a public long-term care faclhty. A
t H igh D
esert, her physicians ordered, against her w
ill, that she be once again force-fed to head off possible starvation. They thought nasogasm
c feeding appropriate because her condition w
as life- threatem
ng and because w ith adequate nutrition she
could possibly live another 15 or 20 years. S
he sued the hospital, askm g the S
uperior C ourt of
Los A ngeles to order the force-feeding halted. B
ut the court refused, saying that she clearly intended suicide and that the state could do w
hatever w as necessary
to preserve her hie. S
he appealed the decision to a higher court and, this tim
e, w on In a 1986 ruling, the C
alifornia C ourt of
A ppeal declared unequw
ocally that com petent adults
have a “constitutionally guaranteed right” to decide for them
selves w hether to subm
it to m edical treatm
ents:
[S ]uch a pauent has the right to refuse any m
edi- cal treatm
ent, even that w hich m
ay save or pro- long her hfe.. T
he right to refuse m edical treat-
m ent IS
basic and fundam ental. It IS
recogm zed as
a part of the right of prw acy protected by both
th e
sta te
a n
d fe
d e
ra l co
n su
tu u
o n
s. Its e xe
r-
cise requw es no one’s approval. It is not m
erely one vote sublect to being overridden by m
edm al
opinion .. A long hne of cases, approved by the
S uprem
e court m C
obbs v. G rant (I 972)… have
held that w here a doctor perform
s treatm ent
m the absence of reform
ed consent, there m s an
actionable battery. T he obw
ous corollary to tN s
principle m s that “a com
petent patient has the legal right to refuse m
e& cal treatm
ent”7
T he central issue in this fam
ous case–both m oral
and legal–Is w hether a com
petent pauent has the right to refuse hfe-sustaining m
edm al treatm
ent In gO
U V
la v S uperior C
The post Paternalism and Patient Autonomy appeared first on Infinite Essays.
Paternalism and Patient Autonomy
Thanks for installing the Bottom of every post plugin by Corey Salzano. Contact me if you need custom WordPress plugins or website design.